The Storm and the Butterfly

Are all models bound to fail?

In the 19th and 20th centuries, standard economic models assumed that people would act in a rational and predictable manner. These models are flawed, of course, for if modern psychology has taught us anything it is that we are massively complex beings who are ultimately in important respects not predictable, often not rational, and certainly often rational in ways that are judged irrational by ‘experts’. We are moreover (and this is less widely understood) not predictable not only in practice but also in principle: i.e. this is not a limitation that can be overcome. For if the human future could be predicted, it would then be deliberately altered. Therefore it cannot be predicted. Human creativity and novelty and our ability to respond to predictions means that our actions cannot possibly by reliably modelled, even in principle.

The same can be said to some extent of natural systems too. Many still consider these to be deterministic systems governed by the strict laws of nature. And indeed, in many cases this is correct, but there are a number of outlying cases which do not conform to this. And they are enormously important. Think of chaos theory, for instance. Think of storms and their preceding butterflies…

Typically these cases involve uncertainty, or indeed complete ignorance which results in a necessarily deficient model. When the outliers that such models cannot model are potentially stormy – i.e. catastrophic – then this and similar sorts of situations result in what are informally called ‘black swans’ by my colleague Nassim Taleb (see for example our joint paper here).

But models are also of course based upon evidence — and so here is another problem with them. One should ask where that evidence comes from; the answer is principally observation and experimentation. But the experiments that were conducted to gather this evidence were also based upon a model; which again was based upon evidence gathered from within a particular model. This ‘self-reinforcing’ nature of models within particular disciplines is called by the great philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn a ‘paradigm’ and the presence of a paradigm is one of the benchmarks for what gets classed as a science (or not). The big problem here though is that the experiment typically only tests for what the model says should be there, and often there is no way to measure anything else that might happen as a result of the experiment. There could be a whole new world of science, or at least a completely different way to look at the same science which we have never encountered because of this.

___

"We should learn to live in a world that we don’t understand, rather than harbouring dangerous ambitions for total explanation and mastery."
___

Normally this isn’t a problem. The paradigm can normally be trusted. But sooner or later, paradigms encounter (or breach) their limits, and break down or require replacement. At the frontier of scientific knowledge, one never knows whether one might be at such a point. Again, this limitation is one that cannot be overcome, by definition.

The principled limit on scientific knowledge about ourselves; ever-present limits on our knowledge even of natural systems; the limits of science itself (at the research frontier); the way that science which builds knowledge is self-reinforcing and so inevitably runs the risk of missing counter-evidence; …these are among the reasons why we should be humble about how much we know. We should recognise, as did Socrates, that often the wisest path is to admit that we are more ignorant than we tend to like to believe. We should accept that we live in a world that in many ways we don’t understand and that we will certainly never ‘fully understand’. We should learn to live in a world that we don’t understand, rather than harbouring hubristic, dangerous ambitions for ‘total’ explanation and mastery.

In light of all this I advocate caution: to be specific, a precautionary approach. We should acknowledge when there are or might be problems with our models and evidence instead of blindly or dogmatically believing in current science above everything else. When we create plans of action we should consult not only the model and the evidence but also the individuals who are experts in philosophy, in statistics, etc. This is not to say that models do not have a use; merely that they should not be the only nor the deciding factor in virtually any debate that matters.

Where the stakes are high, we should err decisively on the side of caution. We should reject ‘expert’ claims to know that such-and-such is safe, when the evidence on which those claims are based is not statistically significant. We must recognise when such evidence does not encompass drastic possible outliers which could turn the whole graph upside down – for example, because it is taken from a hopelessly short time-period, relative to the total risks of the phenomenon in the long view.

When a butterfly can create a storm, invest heavily in storm-protection – without awaiting the ‘evidence’. And, just as important: act swiftly and strongly so as to build down the environmental presence of human pollutants that increase the probability of more storms and worse storms. This is the precautionary approach that public policy must now adopt.

 

Image credit: Yuri Laptev

Latest Releases
Join the conversation

Dzen_o 26 May 2016

"…We should learn to live in a world that we don’t understand, rather than harbouring dangerous ambitions for total explanation and mastery…", etc.

- the article above is next mainstream-philosophical attempt to solve the main epistemological problem – is or not the science adequate to the external [to humans, or, more correctly – to human’s consciousnesses] reality? And the solution is as always – the author chooses the answer “no”; though for such conclusion in the article there are no any reasonable grounds. As well if in the article could be the answer “yes”, it would be ungrounded equally, though.

In the reality the problem is that to solve such question is necessary before to understand – what are at least the notions/ phenomena “[human’s] Consciousness” and “External”, the letter for a consciousness include other consciousnesses and the notion/phenomenon “Matter”.

At that all notions above are Meta-mainstream- philosophical (and Meta- scientific) and so cannot be properly understandable/ defined in framework of recent sciences and the mainstream philosophy; that is possible only in the “The Information as Absolute” conception http://vixra.org/pdf/1402.0173v3.pdf DOI 10.5281/zenodo.34958, where it is rigorously proven that all what exist in our Universe and outside is/are some informational patterns and systems of the patterns that are elements of absolutely fundamental and absolutely infinite “Information” Set.

Our Universe, which consists of informational systems “Matter”, “Alive”, and “Consciousness” is only some sub-Set – when, of course, the systems above are some sub-Sets also.

The main difference of elements of the sub-Set “Consciousness”, i.e. of individual human’s consciousnesses from elements of Matter (material objects and systems of the objects) and living beings, is that the consciousnesses are capable to decode some informational bounds, messages, etc. that happen in the external by using material sensors (eyes, ears, tactile information, etc) data. And at that there is nothing surprising, if some consciousness decodes some bounds, for example – Nature laws – correctly.

I.e. in the reality there is no principal “epistemological problems”, all what is required from scientists is to make experiments and to interpret the experiments outcomes, including by creating scientific models and theories, objectively.

That doesn’t mean, of course, that any theory is adequate to the external – indeed, 99% of attempts to decode some bounds correctly go to baskets. However, this fact doesn’t differ principally from the fact when somebody attempts to understand – what some other somebody says and makes? And at that anything is possible – both adequate and non-adequate understandings. Though in relations between humans there are no principal problems at understanding each other – again, practically equally to cases when humans interact with Matter.

Cheers

PS. The paper “The Information as Absolute” was rejected by near ten mainstream-philosophical journals; possibly including because of that the idea that all/everything is some information seems on first sight as rather strange. But now this idea is rather widely recognized and, for example, New Scientist recently made the special issue with a slogan “Everything is made of information”.
https://www.newscientist.com/round-up/reality/?cmpid=EMP|NSNS|2016-1505-GLOBAL-maywk3|Reality&utm_medium=EMP&utm_source=NSNS&utm_campaign=MayWk3&utm_content=Reality&cmpid
However any article in the issue doesn’t content a reference on the “Information as Absolute” conception, though this fact was proven yet in 2007 …

semcpherson@vwc.edu 5 May 2016

I see this article as another attempt to persuade us that philosophy is relevant to science . Science don't need philosophy to tell it that models have problems; the scientific method is a conservative methodology and we know the flaws in our own work. Scientists are naturally conservative. Thats why we follow the scientific method. Philosophy has a role in public policy debates but it has no role in informing scientists on their methods.